Monografias.com > Economía
Descargar Imprimir Comentar Ver trabajos relacionados

Would the Absence of Copyright Laws Significantly Affect the Quality and Quantity of Literary Output?




Enviado por Julio H.Cole



    "The greatest constraint on your future liberties may
    come not from government but from corporate legal departments
    laboring to protect by force what can no longer be protected by
    practical efficiency or general social
    consent."1

    John Perry Barlow

    1. Introduction
    2. Patents and Copyrights As Property
      Rights
    3. The Case of
      Copyrights
    4. Concluding
      Remarks
    5. Notes

    Introduction

    Patents and copyrights are special forms of immaterial
    property that grant to their owners the exclusive right to
    control the
    production and sale of a specified product–a literary or
    artistic work in the case of copyrights, an invention or
    productive process in the case of patents. Often these concepts
    are subsumed under a broader concept of intellectual property,
    but they are not completely analogous and cannot always be
    justified with the same arguments. The term intellectual
    property
    also covers some other very different concepts, such
    as trademarks. Unfortunately, in recent discussions of these
    topics the concept of intellectual property is often used
    generically, blurring some important practical
    distinctions.

    Patents and Copyrights As Property Rights

    Although the term intellectual property is
    commonly used in the legal field, in economics it is rather
    problematic, since it is difficult to justify this type of
    property right with the same arguments used to justify property
    in tangible goods. According to the economic theory of property
    (following David Hume), society benefits from the delimitation
    and protection of property rights because goods are scarce. There
    is no point in defining property rights over goods when these
    exist in abundance. On the other hand, when goods are scarce and
    property is communal, they are not used efficiently. Private
    property guarantees that scarce goods will be put to their most
    efficient and productive uses.

    From this point of view, however, it is difficult to
    justify intellectual property rights, since these rights do not
    arise from the scarcity of the appropriated objects. Rather, the
    purpose of an intellectual property right is to create a
    scarcity, thereby generating a monopoly rent for the holder of
    the right. In this case, the law does not protect property over a
    scarce good, since the scarcity is created by the law itself. In
    fact, such artificial scarcity is the source of the monopoly
    rents that confer value upon those rights. The big difference
    between intellectual property rights and titles of property over
    tangible goods is that the latter will be scarce even if there
    are no well-defined property rights, whereas in the case of
    patents and copyrights the scarcity only arises after the
    property right is defined.2

    Defenders of patents and copyrights often deny that
    these property rights constitute monopoly privileges. They argue
    instead that the term monopoly is inapplicable in the case
    of patents and copyrights.3 While this may be a matter
    of semantics to some degree, in any event there is no theoretical
    incompatibility between the property and monopoly aspects of
    intellectual property rights.

    However, in practice, these aspects are closely related,
    since the monopolistic nature of patents and copyrights is
    precisely what confers economic value upon them. Obviously, like
    any other monopoly privilege, patents and copyrights can be
    valuable for their owners, though this does not in itself justify
    their existence. Clearly, the owners benefit from patent and
    copyright protection, but the really interesting question is
    whether society at large benefits as well. One important aspect
    of this broader issue can be dealt with in reply to the question
    posed for this controversy.4

    The
    Case of Copyrights

    It should be noted from the outset that the term
    copyright, as currently used, actually comprises a bundle
    of several different rights that have become conflated because of
    the use of a single concept to cover the entire
    bundle.

    The expression used to denote copyright in
    Spanish, French, Italian, and Portuguese (derecho de autor,
    droit d'auter, diritto d'autore, direito do autor
    ) literally
    translates as "author's rights." The concept of author's rights
    encompasses a broader range of rights in addition to the notion
    of copyright in the narrower sense (i.e., the right to control
    reproduction of the work). Such broader rights include the
    so-called moral rights
    of the author, which view literary and artistic works as
    extensions of the author's personality. The moral rights of the
    author encompass the following protections: (1) the right to be
    identified as the creator of the work (so-called paternity rights
    of authorship and protections against plagiarism), and (2)
    protections against unauthorized alterations or mutilations of
    the work (so-called integrity rights of authorship).

    As opposed to mere copyright, these two moral rights of
    authorship have always been regarded as inalienable and
    perpetual. (A third moral right is also recognized, namely, the
    right to withhold publication, which is an aspect of a broader
    right to privacy, although it is not always clear whether it
    should be regarded as perpetual or whether it applies only to
    living authors. Should society be bound by an author's wishes
    after his death?)

    Opposition to copyright in the narrower sense does not
    imply opposition to the moral right of authorship, which is a
    long-standing legal concept. Copyright, on the other hand, is a
    fairly recent notion that dates from, roughly, the invention of
    the printing press. Whether or not the right to control the
    reproduction of creative works is viewed as a natural right of
    authors, the fact is that prior to the invention of printing this
    right was not regarded as implicit in the concept of
    authorship.

    Copyright law was created by specific acts of
    legislation. In fact, every extension of the scope of copyright
    law to cover new productions resulting from technological
    innovations (such as photography, phonographic recordings of
    musical creations, film productions, computer software, and so forth) has
    required special legislation to that effect, since these
    extensions did not arise naturally from judicial decisions. As
    the following extensive quotation illustrates, courts have simply
    been unwilling to apply a concept created specifically for the
    case of printed books to these new situations:

    The concept of copyright is rooted in the technology of
    print. The recognition of a copyright and the practice of paying
    royalties emerged with the printing press…. Copyright was
    a specific adaptation to a specific technology, and to the
    problems and opportunities it created. The law recognized that.
    The landmark case in the United States was White Smith v. Apollo
    (1908). It denied protection to piano rolls or sound recordings
    because they were not "writings" in tangible form readable by a
    human being. That common law concept of copyright excluded from
    protection many new technologies of communication since 1908. But
    the motion picture industry, the recording industry, and more
    recently the broadcasting industry have persuaded Congress to
    extend various protections to them, since courts were not willing
    to do so…. However, with the arrival of radio and
    electronic reproduction, and now photocopy reproduction, the
    concept becomes inappropriate.

    There is no easy way to keep tabs on the numerous
    reproductions in somewhat variable form that can take place in
    innumerable locations with these new technologies. The analogy is
    to word-of-mouth
    communications in the 18th century, not to the print shop of that
    period. Nonetheless, information and publishing industries whose
    welfare and survival depends on finding some way to charge for
    their information processing services have latched on to
    copyright protection under statute law and are trying to get the
    courts or the Congress to extend copyright protection to
    computerized data, photocopies, and telereproduction.

    Though recognizing that in those technologies the
    existent copyright law is basically unenforceable, they
    nonetheless grab on to whatever frail reed it may provide rather
    than turn to the even frailer reed of trying to invent, and to
    get into legislation, some entirely new as-yet undevised system
    for rewarding the creators of information…. the U. S.
    Congress passed a new copyright law in 1976, which was designed
    to solve all the new problems of copyright for cable television,
    photocopying, and computers. It has solved few if any of
    them….

    How inappropriate the concept of copyright is to
    computer communications becomes evident as we examine how the law
    has to squirm to deal with the simplest problems…. the process
    of computer communication entails processing of texts that are
    partly controlled by people and partly automatic. They are
    happening all over the system. Some of the text is never visible
    but is only stored electronically: Some is flashed briefly on a
    terminal display; some is printed out in hard
    copy….

    The receivers may be individuals and clearly identified,
    or they may be passers-by with access but
    whose access is never
    recorded; the passer-by may only look, as a reader browsing
    through a book, or he may make an automatic copy; sometimes the
    program will record that, sometimes it will not. To try to apply
    the concept of copyright to all these stages and actors would
    require a most elaborate set of regulations. It has none of the
    simplicity of checking what copies rolled off a printing
    press….

    One would like to compensate an author if a computer
    terminal is used as a printing press to run off numerous copies
    of a valuable text. One would not like to impose any control as
    someone works at a terminal in the role of a reader and checks
    back and forth through various files. The boundary, however, is
    impossible to draw. In the new technology of interactive
    computing, the reader, the writer, the bookseller, and the
    printer have become one. In the old technology of printing, one
    could have a right to free press for the reader and the writer
    but try to enforce copyright on the printer and the bookseller.
    That distinction will no longer work, anymore than it would ever
    have worked in the past on conversation. Those whose livelihood
    is at stake in copyright do not like that kind of
    comment.

    They contend that creative work must be compensated.
    Indeed it must…. But the system must be practical to
    work.… in an era of infinitely varied, automated text
    manipulation there is no reasonable way to count copies and
    charge royalties on them…. It may be very unfair to
    authors. It may have a profoundly negative effect on some aspects
    of culture, and in any case, whether positive or negative, it may
    change things considerably.

    If it becomes more difficult for authors and artists to
    be paid by a royalty scheme, more of them will seek salaried
    bases from which to work. Some may try to get paid by personal
    appearances or other auxiliaries to fame. Or the highly
    illustrated, well-bound book may acquire a special significance
    if the mere words of the text are hard to protect. Or one may try
    to sell subscriptions to a continuing service….

    These are the kinds of considerations one must think
    about in speculating about the consequences for culture of a
    world where the royalty-carrying unit copy is no longer easy to
    protect in many of the domains where it has been
    dominant…. it is clear that with photocopiers and
    computers, copyright is an anachronism. Like many other
    unenforceable laws that we keep on the statute books from the
    past, this one may be with us for some time to come, but with
    less and less effect.5

    The final passages from this long quotation suggest the
    intriguing possibility that, in arguing whether authors
    should have a copyright over their creations, we may be
    posing what will increasingly become a moot question.
    Technological developments in certain areas–photocopiers,
    video and
    sound recording, computer scanning, and so forth–are making
    it harder to enforce claims to intellectual property. At some
    point, we might just have to give up trying to enforce such
    claims.6

    But what would happen if copyrights were suddenly
    relaxed? Since the main utilitarian argument for
    maintaining copyright protection is that it stimulates literary
    and artistic creation, it is fair to inquire whether the absence
    of legally protected copyrights would significantly affect the
    quality and quantity of literary output.

    To answer this question, we should note first that most
    authors never make much money writing books, and some actually
    underwrite the printing costs of their own works. Other authors
    are willing to accept payment for their intellectual property in
    terms of copies of their work (often in the form of off-prints of
    journal articles). A great deal of scientific and academic
    writing is of this kind. For many of these authors, writing for
    publication is a way to increase their brand-name capital in
    order to obtain higher incomes from other activities.

    Still other authors are interested primarily in
    spreading their views, so they would presumably have no interest
    in discouraging the reproduction of their writings, provided, of
    course, that their authorship is acknowledged. These authors
    would be quite happy if others were willing to reprint their work
    at no cost to themselves. The output of this type of writing
    evidently would not be affected much by the absence of copyright
    protection.

    A second type of author writes for a living. If there is
    no other appropriate way to reward this person, then the absence
    of copyright protection would most likely reduce his or her total
    literary output. The real question is whether maintaining
    copyright protection is the only way to guarantee an income for
    this type of author. Sir Arnold Plant, an early twentieth-century
    English economist, believed that authors would find a way to sell
    their product if a demand truly exists for it.7
    Notice, however, that the mere existence of copyright protection
    does not create this demand, it only provides a means to
    monopolize a demand once it has been found to
    exist.

    It is impossible to know a priori what kind of
    market structure would dominate in a different legal climate,
    though possibly there would be greater reliance on salaried
    writers for subscription-type publications with content being
    "given away" as loss-leaders to stimulate sales of other
    products.8 Moreover, as Pool suggested, there might be
    greater reliance on collateral sources of income, such as
    personal appearances, lectures, consulting, live
    performances,9 and so on. Whether alternative market
    arrangements would fully compensate the loss of income currently
    derived from copyright is an open question. Best-selling writers
    and composers might very well earn less money in a world without
    copyright protection. If so, then the quantity of literary
    and artistic output would most likely be lower. But precisely how
    much lower would be impossible to predict.

    Plant argued that the absence of copyright protection
    would likely result in a smaller number of titles
    published.10 If true, this would not necessarily be
    bad, since most people seem to want more good books at lower
    prices and not necessarily more titles. Plant held that the
    copyright system has a somewhat perverse consequence because it
    encourages the publication of a broader range of titles, but not
    enough copies of the books people really want to read. Due to the
    nature of the industry, a publisher
    cannot be sure of the success of a new title, and, in fact, most
    titles do not even cover the printing costs. Nevertheless, when a
    title is successful it can be quite profitable, and these profits
    subsidize the losses from unsuccessful titles.

    Since a publisher cannot know beforehand which new
    titles will be successful, publishing can be compared to a
    lottery. To make money on successful titles, a publisher has to
    take a chance on many different titles, most of which will likely
    be unsuccessful. Copyright affects this situation by increasing
    the profitability of successful titles. In terms of the lottery,
    copyright protection increases the prize without affecting, on
    the other hand, the risks involved. Ceteris paribus, we
    expect that with equal risks, a larger prize will induce a player
    to buy more tickets. Therefore, more titles will be published
    under a copyright system, but the resulting monopoly position
    guarantees that the books people really want (the successful
    titles) will be published in smaller quantities and at higher
    prices.

    Concluding Remarks

    Issues related to intellectual property are becoming
    increasingly important in policy discussions. Recent
    technological developments–such as computer software
    (particularly the question of so-called Internet patents) and
    biotechnologies (in terms of the "patenting of
    life-forms")–have created whole new classes of products
    that pose significant problems for the definition and
    delimitation of property rights.11 On the other hand,
    some of these technological innovations, such as downloadable
    MP3 computer
    files, are making it harder to enforce even conventional forms of
    intellectual property seen, for example, in musical recordings.
    The strains and stresses that these newer technologies impose on
    current intellectual property law are resulting in calls for
    tougher enforcement of existing legal mechanisms.

    The United States government has for several years taken
    the lead internationally in pressuring other countries to
    strengthen their intellectual property laws and make them conform
    more closely to current United States standards. In light of such
    developments, now is as good a time as any to rethink the concept
    of intellectual property rights. Perhaps, instead of proposing
    reforms to strengthen patents and copyrights, we should be
    moving in the opposite direction?

    Notes

    1. John Perry Barlow, "The Economy of Ideas: A Framework
      for Patents and Copyrights in the Digital Age (Everything You
      Know About Intellectual Property Is Wrong)," Wired 2.03
      (March 1994). This document can be accessed at: .
    2. Perhaps the clearest statement of this argument can
      be attributed to the English economist, Sir Arnold Plant, from
      a 1934 paper titled, "The Economic Theory Concerning Patents
      for Inventions," in Selected Economic Essays and
      Addresses
      (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1974),
      35—36. For more on Plant's economic thought, see R. H.
      Coase, "Professor Sir Arnold Plant: His Ideas and Influence,"
      in The Unfinished Agenda: Essays on the Political Economy of
      Government Policy in Honour of Arthur Seldon,
      ed. M. J.
      Anderson (London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 1986),
      81—90.
    3. For instance, Michael Novak, The Fire of
      Invention: Civil Society and the Future of the Corporation

      (New York: Free Press, 1997), 69, 144.
    4. Though they share many common features, patents and
      copyrights provide different types of protection, and they have
      quite separate legislative histories. My discussion in the
      following section will focus on copyrights and is largely based
      on Sir Arnold Plant, "The Economic Aspects of Copyright in
      Books," in Selected Economic Essays and Addresses
      (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1974), 57—86,
      and Robert M. Hurt, "The Economic Rationale of Copyright,"
      American Economic Review 56 (May 1966): 421—32. A
      classic paper by Fritz Machlup and Edith T. Penrose, "The
      Patent Controversy in the Nineteenth Century," Journal of
      Economic History
      10 (May 1950): 1—29, provides a good
      introduction to the historical literature on patents. For a
      more recent critique of the patent concept, see Pierre
      Desrochers, "On the Abuse of Patents as Economic Indicators,"
      Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 1 (Winter 1998):
      51—74. On the general issue of intellectual property, see
      the excellent articles by Tom G. Palmer, "Are Patents and
      Copyrights Morally Justified?," Harvard Journal of Law and
      Public Policy
      13 (Summer 1990): 817—65; "Intellectual
      Property: A Non-Posnerian Law and Economics Approach,"
      Hamline Law Review 12 (Spring 1989): 261—304; and
      N. Stephan Kinsella, "Against Intellectual Property,"
      Journal of Libertarian Studies 15 (Spring 2001):
      1—54.
    5. Ithiel de Sola Pool, Technologies Without
      Boundaries: On Telecommunications in a Global Age

      (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990),
      254—59.
    6. We may have already reached this point in the case of
      musical recordings.
    7. Plant, "The Economic Aspects of Copyright in Books,"
      61.
    8. This is the business model underlying contemporary
      journalism, which essentially hires staff writers to help sell
      the main product: advertising. There are many other examples of
      this type of arrangement. For instance, early radio
      broadcasters were subsidized by radio manufacturers, who were
      willing to lose money on broadcasting to stimulate demand for
      radio sets. Incidentally, it seems to me that this example
      describes well how the market would solve the problem of
      computer software in the absence of copyright. It is often
      claimed that if software could be copied freely, then software
      developers would have no incentive to create it. Note, however,
      that hardware manufact-urers would have an incentive to
      support software development (and, perhaps, even give it away
      for free), since the availability of more and better software
      increases the demand for hardware.
    9. In the case of music it is interesting to note that,
      prior to the development of the phonograph, copyright over
      music applied only to sheet music; i.e., it did not extend to
      the musical performance. It is an open question whether the
      gradual extension of copyright to cover not only musical
      recordings but any kind of public performance, has
      resulted in increased quantity and quality of musical
      composition. In any case, if musical recordings could be freely
      copied (which, in practice, increasingly happens to be the case
      now due to the development of MP3 computer files), musicians
      would still have an incentive to compose and record music to
      stimulate the demand for live performances.
    10. Plant, "The Economic Aspects of Copyright in Books,"
      72, 80.
    11. On patenting life, see John H. Barton, "Patenting
      Life," Scientific American 264 (March 1991):
      18—24. As for Internet patents, recall that in October
      1999 Priceline.com sued Microsoft's
      Expedia group for infringement of its patented "name your own
      price" auction system, while Amazon.com, the leading Internet
      book retailer, sued its main rival, Barnes&Nobel.com, for
      infringement of its patented "one-click" ordering system. See
      Kevin G. Rivette and David Kline, "Discovering New Value in
      Intellectual Property," Harvard Business Review 78
      (January-February 2000): 54—66.

    Julio H. Cole

    Professor of Economics Universidad
    Francisco Marroquín. Guatemala

    Nota al lector: es posible que esta página no contenga todos los componentes del trabajo original (pies de página, avanzadas formulas matemáticas, esquemas o tablas complejas, etc.). Recuerde que para ver el trabajo en su versión original completa, puede descargarlo desde el menú superior.

    Todos los documentos disponibles en este sitio expresan los puntos de vista de sus respectivos autores y no de Monografias.com. El objetivo de Monografias.com es poner el conocimiento a disposición de toda su comunidad. Queda bajo la responsabilidad de cada lector el eventual uso que se le de a esta información. Asimismo, es obligatoria la cita del autor del contenido y de Monografias.com como fuentes de información.

    Categorias
    Newsletter